Author Topic: Allah, Queen, and Country: Sharia gets an unlikely boost in the UK.  (Read 547 times)

0 Members and 1 Guest are viewing this topic.

Rich

  • Guest
Allah, Queen, and Country
Sharia gets an unlikely boost in the UK.

by Joseph Loconte
02/13/2008 12:00:00 AM



LAST WEEK THE ARCHBISHOP of Canterbury, the spiritual leader of the worldwide Anglican Communion, generated a tsunami of criticism by welcoming the partial adoption of Islamic Sharia law in the United Kingdom. "If what we want socially," said Rowan Williams, "is a pattern of relations in which a plurality of diverse and overlapping affiliations work for a common good . . . it seems unavoidable." The only truly unavoidable thing was that an apology from the archbishop would be forthcoming. Whether the continued decline in the influence of Christianity in Britain is also unavoidable remains an open question.

The mea culpa arrived earlier this week, somewhat garbled, in a speech before the church's General Synod. Williams offered to "take responsibility" for his remarks, but also insisted upon his right to make them. "I believe quite strongly," he said, "that it is not inappropriate for a pastor of the Church of England to address issues around the perceived concerns of other religious communities and to try and bring them into better public focus."

The cataclysmic failure of that effort--two members of the Synod are demanding that Williams resign, while his predecessor, Lord George Carey, calls the plan "disastrous for the nation"--cannot simply be blamed on the archbishop's tin ear for politics. The problem, shared by much of the Anglican establishment, is a culture of political correctness that is at once too generous and too stingy: an eagerness to overlook the staggering problems in Islamic thought with regard to democratic rights, but a reluctance to claim any decisive role for biblical religion in the formation and defense of those rights.

The backdrop of the archbishop's self-inflicted crisis is the growth of a militant Muslim population in the United Kingdom, alongside the appearance of Sharia tribunals for the wider Islamic community. They operate mostly informally, offering rulings in civil cases on everything from divorce disputes to property rights. Williams apparently wants these private tribunals, such as the Islamic Sharia Council in east London, to be legitimized--and regulated--by the state. They would offer a "supplementary jurisdiction," where Muslims could decide whether to resolve civil disputes in secular courts or within their own communities. "There needs to be access to recognized authority acting for a religious group," he said. "It is uncomfortably true that this introduces into our thinking about law what some would see as a 'market' element, a competition for loyalty."

The notion of a "competition for loyalty" is not merely an uncomfortable idea in a democracy--it is a poisonous idea. It ignores the genius and achievements of the Western legal tradition, especially its Anglo-American expression.

The concept of equal justice under the law was hammered out over centuries in Great Britain and the United States--from debates in the House of Commons to the sermons and pamphlet wars of religious leaders and activists. It proceeded from the Christian conception of "natural rights" and "natural law," the belief that every person, by virtue of his or her humanity, possessed inalienable rights and obligations. It was an Englishman, John Locke--in his Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration--who helped make these ideas the touchstone of liberal democracy. And, as Cambridge historian John Dunn argues, Locke's political conclusions were "saturated with Christian assumptions" about human dignity.

Nevertheless, Locke and his circle of reformers insisted that they were defending "what is common to all men." To be a citizen in a liberal democracy means to endorse, or to give one's loyalty, to the common good. In political terms, that requires impartial justice under the law. Most religious believers in the West have learned to uphold this political doctrine in practice, while still reserving their ultimate loyalties for their Creator.

Now, along comes the Archbishop of Canterbury, who suggests that this principle of civic peace and social justice is either outdated or overrated. Williams worries about "an unqualified secular legal monopoly" that marginalizes religious view points. He fears a breakdown in social solidarity if, amid massive religious pluralism, the state fails to offer "a higher level of attention to religious identity." Thus, there is "a bit of a risk" in the democratic idea that "everyone stands before the public tribunal on exactly equal terms."

If risk management is the archbishop's goal, he is choosing a path guaranteed to maximize the danger. Williams admits that allowing Sharia as an alternative source of family law, for example, could reinforce "some of the most repressive and retrograde elements" in Islamic communities. Yet he offers no practical plan for how this would be avoided. (Last week, the London-based Centre for Social Cohesion released a report warning of the growth of religiously rooted "honour-based" violence in the United Kingdom.) And he provides little guidance about Sharia interpretations that condone polygamy, wife-beating, rape, forced marriages, or genital mutilation--all cultural problems in countries where Sharia law holds sway.

The archbishop is careful to explain that no Islamic "supplementary" court could deny citizens rights guaranteed under secular British law. Yet this is precisely what Islamic militants, keen to impose Sharia everywhere, are noisily seeking in Britain. Williams defends his approach as a "transformative accommodation" by government toward religious communities. Yet the likely consequences of the transformation he imagines--an explosion in renegade Sharia tribunals, deepening social isolation, the declining moral authority of English common law--don't figure into his calculations.

Many liberals and secularists view the entire effort to accommodate religious belief with disdain. The Guardian complains that the latest flap proves that religion "would be better entirely excluded" from public life. Writing in Slate, Christopher Hitchens lauds the democratic work of "centuries of civilization"--yet fatuously assumes that strident secularism did the heavy lifting.

Nonsense. Just recall the history-making Somerset Case of 1771, in which a British judge used a writ of habeas corpus to free an American slave brought to England from Virginia. Buoyed by evangelicals and other abolitionists, Lord William Mansfield declared slavery an "odious" condition unknown to English law and set James Somerset free. British law trumped the American practice--a bracing defense of political equality, inseparable from the biblical moral tradition. "[It] is not fit to be taught as a secular doctrine," writes political philosopher Jeremy Waldron. "It is a conception of equality that makes no sense except in the light of a particular account of the relation between man and God."

The difficult fact is that Islam has yet to show convincingly that its conception of God supports the human-rights ideals of liberal societies--from freedom of religion to the rights of women. The question that remains, the question ignored by the Archbishop of Canterbury, is how his Sharia scheme could possibly hasten this great democratic task.



Joseph Loconte is a senior fellow at Pepperdine University's School of Public Policy, a commentator on religion for National Public Radio, and a frequent contributor to THE DAILY STANDARD.

? Copyright 2008, News Corporation, Weekly Standard, All Rights Reserved.